Friday, August 25, 2017

Originalism vs. The Living Constitution: Suppose Both Are Right?



I. Art. V as it reads today:


 The Congress, whenever two thirds of both houses shall deem it necessary, shall propose amendments to this Constitution, or, on the application of the legislatures of two thirds of the several states, shall call a convention for proposing amendments, which, in either case, shall be valid to all intents and purposes, as part of this Constitution, when ratified by the legislatures of three fourths of the several states, or by conventions in three fourths thereof, as the one or the other mode of ratification may be proposed by the Congress; provided that no amendment which may be made prior to the year one thousand eight hundred and eight shall in any manner affect the first and fourth clauses in the ninth section of the first article; and that no state, without its consent, shall be deprived of its equal suffrage in the Senate.

II.  Judge Robert Bork on the "temptation" of the judiciary:

 In law, the moment of temptation is the moment of choice, when a judge realizes that in the case before him his strongly held view of justice, his political and moral imperative, is not embodied in a statute or in any provision of the Constitution. He must then choose between his version of justice and abiding by the American form of government. Yet the desire to do justice, whose nature seems to him obvious, is compelling, while the concept of constitutional process is abstract, rather arid, and the abstinence it counsels unsatisfying. To give in to temptation, this one time, solves an urgent human problem, and a faint crack appears in the American foundation. A judge has begun to rule where a legislator should.

III. Madison in Federalist 45

The powers delegated by the proposed Constitution to the federal government, are few and defined. Those which are to remain in the State governments are numerous and indefinite. The former will be exercised principally on external objects, as war, peace, negotiation, and foreign commerce; with which last the power of taxation will, for the most part, be connected. The powers reserved to the several States will extend to all the objects which, in the ordinary course of affairs, concern the lives, liberties, and properties of the people, and the internal order, improvement, and prosperity of the State.





IV. My Proposed Amended Version of Art. V:

 1. The words and phrases of this Constitution shall be interpreted according to their ordinary meaning at the time of their enactment, which meaning shall remain the same until changed pursuant to Article V; nor shall such meaning be altered by reference to the law of nations or the laws of other nations.
[Note: I borrowed most of this language from Randy Barnett’s proposed federalism amendment]
2.  Whenever a majority of either House of Congress shall deem it necessary, such House shall propose Amendments to this Constitution, which shall be valid to all Intents and Purposes, as Part of this Constitution, when ratified by the Legislatures of three-fourths of the several States.
3. Whenever the Legislatures of any five of the several States shall deem it necessary, such Legislatures shall propose Amendments to this Constitution, which shall be valid to all Intents and Purposes, when ratified by the Legislatures of three-fourths of the several States.
4. Congress, on the application of the legislatures of two thirds of the several States, shall call a convention for proposing amendments, which shall be valid to all Intents and Purposes, as part of this Constitution, when ratified by the legislatures of three fourths of the several States.
5. Anything to the contrary herein notwithstanding, no state, without its consent, shall be deprived of its equal suffrage in the Senate.

Thursday, August 24, 2017

Bill Brennan Says




Here are some passages from Justice Brennan's contribution to the "great debate:"









1. "Our amended Constitution is the lodestar for our aspirations. Like every text worth reading, it is not crystalline. The phrasing is broad and the limitations of its provisions are not clearly marked. Its majestic generalities and ennobling pronouncements are both luminous and obscure. This ambiguity of course calls forth interpretation, the interaction of reader and text. The encounter with the constitutional text has been, in many senses, my life's work."






2. "We Justices are certainly aware that we are not final because we are infallible; we know that we are infallible only because we are final."






3. "When Justices interpret the Constitution they speak for their community, not for themselves alone. The act of interpretation must be undertaken with full consciousness that it is, in a very real sense, the community's interpretation that is sought. Justices are not platonic guardians appointed to wield authority according to their personal moral predelictions."






4. Which "community" supplies the interpretation Justice Brennan then adopts as law? He tells us more when discussing his view that capital punishment is "under all circumstances" unconstitutional:


"This is an interpretation to which a majority of my fellow Justices--not to mention, it would seem, a majority of my fellow countryman--does not subscribe...I mentioned earlier the judge's role in seeking out the community's interpretation of the Constitutional text. Yet, again in my judgment, when a Justice perceives an interpretation of the text to have departed so far from its essential meaning, that Justice is bound, by a larger constitutional duty to the community, to expose the departure and point toward a different path. On this issue, the death penalty, I hope to embody a community striving for human dignity for all, although perhaps not yet arrived."


When a Justice seeks to embody the values of a future, ideal community, whose values does he look to in defining what kind of future community is the ideal?


5. Justice Brennan reads the Constitution's majestic generalities and ennobling pronouncements as "a sublime oration on the dignity of man," and as therefore somehow creating a right to human dignity.


Is it possible for the Court to apply a "right to human dignity." For example, in the context of capital punishment does "a constitutional vision of human dignity" require capital punishment in order to reflect the human dignity of the victim of the heinous crime, or prohibit capital punishment in order to reflect the human dignity of the convicted killer? Does the vision of human dignity require government to prohibit abortion to reflect the human dignity of human life in the womb, or does it protect the right of women to choose to terminate a pregnancy as a reflection of the human dignity and autonomy of women (and what of the human dignity of the father of the child in the womb, whose views about this matter of life or death are contrary to those of the mother)?

Bob Bork Says



Here are some interesting passages from Bob Bork's contribution to the "great deabte:"




1. "The hard fact is, however, that there are no guidelines outside the Constitution that can control a judge once he abandons the lawyer's task of interpretation. There may be a natural law, but we are not agreed upon what it is, and there is no such law that gives definite answers to a judge trying to decide a case....The truth is that the judge who looks outside the Constitution always looks inside himself and nowhere else."




2. "Noninterpretivism--activism--is said to be the means by which courts add to constitutional freedom and never subtract from it. That is wrong. Among our constitutional freedoms or rights, clearly given in the text, is the power to govern ourselves democratically....G.K. Chesterton might have been addressing this very controversy when he wrote: 'What is the good of telling a community it has every liberty except the liberty to make laws? The liberty to make laws is what constitutes a free people.'"




3. "If noninterpretivism is to be respectable...when [scholars and Justices] address the public, they should say, frankly, 'No, that decision does not come out of the written or historical Constitution. It is based upon a moral choice the judges made, and here is why it is a good choice, and here is why judges are entitled to make it for you.'"




4. "In law, the moment of temptation is the moment of choice, when a judge realizes that in the case before him his strogly held views of justice, his political and moral imperative, is not embodied in a statute or in any provision of the Constitution. He must then choose between his version of justice and abiding by the American form of government. Yet the desire to do justice, whose nature seems to him obvious, is compelling, while the concept of constitutional process is abstract, rather arid, and the abstinence it counsels unsatisfying. To give in to temptation, this one time, solves an urgent human problem, and a faint crack appears in the American foundation. A judge has begun to rule where a legislator should."